This is the second of three posts in a
series.
In “Suffer the little children,” Part I, I offered an overview of the report to General
Convention [of The Episcopal Church] of its Task Force on the Study of Marriage.
I included an annotated table of contents of Appendix I of that report, which
provides seven essays on marriage. I distinguished between two forms of
marriage equality defended in those essays, the first of which is a good thing
and has been achieved, though tentatively for now, the second of which would be
unfortunate.
In this Part II,
I focus on a mistake in the argument of Essay 1, found especially on pp. 21-27,
and I offer brief comments on pp. 37-38 and p. 42. That mistake made in Essay 1
is evident in the following claim:
The
emphasis on procreation and children – however important the former and however
crucial the welfare of the latter to human society – primarily as a purpose or
end, relies on an ethic at odds with the principle outlined above, which is
that people are to be treated as ends in themselves, rather than as means to
another end, however good that end might be. (p. 22)
The authors of
Essay 1 suggest and apparently suppose that there is only one alternative to a
Kantian, deontological ethic, which among other things urges respect for individuals
as “ends in themselves” (introduced on p. 21). That alternative is a
utilitarian ethic (see p. 24, para. 4). In utilitarianism, the greatest good is
to be pursued sometimes, notoriously, at the cost of individuals who – from the
perspective of a Kantian ethic – are used as mere means to the happiness of the
greatest number of people.
But this is a mistake.
The authors omit the alternative on which much catholic moral theology has been
based for centuries: an Aristotelian, teleological account of human flourishing
(from the 4th century before the common era) and its Christian
elaboration by St. Thomas Aquinas (from the 13th century). The
authors of Essay 1 seem to think, or at least to suggest, that the only real alternative
ethical theories for understanding the purposes of marriage are from 18th
and 19th century northern Europe during and after the Enlightenment.
* * *
The principal
practical question for now is whether to eliminate the statement of purposes
from the marriage canon, including reference to procreation and the nurture of
children, next presumably to eliminate them from the marriage rite itself, and perhaps
finally altogether from the conversation. The first of two resolutions proposed
by the Task Force would revise the marriage canon, dropping the statement of
purposes of marriage (Title I Canon 18, Section 3.f., and see BCP p. 423).
I will focus on
the nurture of children, because same-sex couples as well as mixed-sex couples
may nurture children. Nonetheless, when a woman commits to a long pregnancy and
postpartum recovery, this is a substantial commitment and should not be discounted,
not least because some normal activities and enjoyments must be foregone or
slowed during that 12-18 month period. I do not intend in any way to dishonor
such a commitment. All of us, including Jesus, owe a profound debt of gratitude
to our mothers for making this sacrifice for us.
In Essay 1,
Section 3, “The Ethics of Marriage,” the authors cite the Kantian ethic as a
way of understanding what we pledge in the Baptismal Covenant (BCP, p. 305),
when we promise to respect the dignity of every human being. And Kant’s notion
of treating others as ends in themselves rather than simply as means to one’s
own or others’ ends might be a good fit here. No one is to be used for the sake
of others. Everyone is treated with respect and dignity.
But the authors recommit
to their mistake noted earlier in another subsection of Essay 1, Section 3,
“Union of heart, body, and mind” (p. 22). They claim that there is “significant
tension” between the statement in the prologue about procreation and other
purposes of marriage (BCP, p. 423), on the one hand, and the vows the couple
make orally in the service itself (BCP, p. 427), on the other hand. The former
concerns products of the marriage, according to the authors, while the latter
concerns the living out of marriage itself. It’s a distinction between goods
extrinsic to the marriage and those intrinsic to it (p. 24). The vows relate to
the couple themselves (p. 25).
We can leave
aside that, according to Canon I.18.3, subsections d. - g., the couple must sign
a written declaration of their agreement with the words uttered during the rite
in the prologue. The vows the couple make orally to each other in the ritual
have been prefaced by, or will be followed by, written agreement to the
statement of purposes, of which the couple and the body assembled are reminded
in the prologue.
Is there in fact
“significant tension” between the statement of purposes of marriage and the
vows themselves? We could answer “yes” if the only way to understand the
statement of purposes is according to a utilitarian ethic, set at odds against
a Kantian understanding of the vows.
On one, perhaps
the most plausible understanding of the utilitarian perspective, the goal to be
achieved by moral conduct, the greatest happiness of the greatest number, may
well be extrinsic to the means for achieving the pleasures that are to be summed
up to equal that happiness. Think of the way prize money is extrinsic to a
contest, or the way an object purchased is extrinsic to the means used to earn
the money for it, say, during a summer lawn care job or by waiting tables.
The authors
suggest that the goals of procreation and the nurture of children are in this
way extrinsic to the marriage of the couple. This seems a stretch.
In the three
sections that follow, I will describe how some goods of activities or
practices, such as married life, can be intrinsic to them, how we should think
of marriage as a foundational part of a multi-level set of circles of affection
and mutual support, and how the Kantian idea of treating people as ends in
themselves is less suitable to a Christian ethic of marriage than an
Aristotelian idea of true friendship.
The overall
point is that the authors of Essay 1 have omitted the ethical perspective that
is best or at least much better suited to our understanding of Christian
marriage, as if it doesn’t exist, and thus their argument for why we should
eliminate the purposes of marriage from our marriage canon and/or rite is
unpersuasive.
* * *
On the
Aristotelian, teleological understanding of purposes, though some goods are
extrinsic to the activities that achieve them, some are intrinsic. Instead of
the relation between prize money and the contest, think of the fulfillment made possible in an intimate conversation in which two people
make themselves vulnerable to each other and support each other. Or consider the
enjoyment of activities like playing cards or chess or basketball, or
gardening, or playing a guitar – any activity you find challenging but
absorbing, and that draws on your strengths.
Those enjoyments
are intrinsic to their activities. They are not a product, really. They are
parts of the activities themselves, completing them, as Aristotle says (see
esp. Nicomachean Ethics, Book X, Ch.
4, Sec. 5). The enjoyment and fulfillment those activities provide are not
separable, not extrinsic. The prize money and the object purchased could be got
some other way, but these particular enjoyments could not. The nurture of
children, the enjoyments and fulfillments it provides, can be part of and
“complete” the practice of marriage. Of course there are frustrations. Of
course some people are better at it than others, given their temperaments and
their own childhood experiences. Of course marriage does not necessarily involve
the nurture of children.
But the nurture
of children is not essentially extrinsic to the activities that make Christian marriage
a Christian practice – whether children are nurtured by same-sex or mixed-sex
couples, or by those whose spouses are deceased or have left. The nurture of
children is not a merely coincidental byproduct of the practice of Christian
marriage, the way prize money might be.
There is a
bigger picture as well. In the next section I describe briefly what a
teleological understanding of the purposes of marriage might involve, taking
that bigger picture into account.
* * *
The statement of
purposes currently in our marriage rite and marriage canon is an amended form
of the 1949 declaration of intent signed by the couple (then in Canon I.17.3).
No American Book of Common Prayer had
included a statement of purposes until the 1979 Book. But revisions to the
canons in 1949 yielded a statement of the purposes of marriage that read as
follows (quoting from Marion J. Hatchett, 1995, Commentary on the American Prayer Book, p. 433):
We
believe it [marriage] is for the purpose of mutual fellowship, encouragement,
and understanding, for the procreation (if it may be) of children, and their
physical and spiritual nurture, for the safeguarding and benefit of society.
In Essay 5 on
the history of the marriage canon, the only 1949 revisions discussed concern
divorce and remarriage. This is part of an argument that marriage has changed
even in The Episcopal Church. But Essay 5 leaves unmentioned the 1949 revisions
involving inserting a declaration of agreement to such a statement of the
purposes of marriage.
Our current,
1979 version dropped “for the safeguarding and benefit of society.” That
safeguarding and benefit of society frame the bigger picture, the larger
context. They foster the common good, the mutual flourishing of an entire
society that is a goal or telos of
the moral and ethical life, on an Aristotelian account (see Nicomachean Ethics, Book I, Ch. 7, Secs.
15-16 and Book X, Ch. 9, Secs. 6-11).
An ordering of
goods, very roughly stated, picking up on the 1949 canon, would go something
like this: (5) the safeguarding and benefit of society and the mutual
flourishing it promotes are to be fostered through the cooperative activities (4)
of communities such as cities and villages, (3) of civic associations and clubs
and of religious congregations and groups of congregations, (2) of clans
related by birth or other affiliation and extended family groups, and (1) of nuclear
families. Nuclear families are a primary or the basic unit of social
organization in this set of circles of affection and mutual support. They are 1
within 2 within 3 within 4 within 5. Separate out 1 as isolable and
independent, and the whole thing falls apart – and then we look out for our own,
and not for others.
So, for
instance, nuclear families, religious congregations, and villages and cities
ideally work together so that everyone is supported, everyone is treated with
dignity, everyone is brought through healthy development in childhood to a
flourishing adulthood. This involves safe neighborhoods and/or associations in
which children may explore relationships with others, learning to get along
with different people. It involves positive adult role models for children
beyond their own parents or care-givers. And it involves the social
institutions that support children and their families, such as recreational
leagues, religious congregations, and stores and shops that provide staples for
daily living (see, e.g., William Julius Wilson, 1987, The Truly Disadvantaged).
Cooperation on a
very large scale is required for everyone to be treated with dignity, for
everyone to flourish. Give up that large-scale cooperative network, and you
consign those children who are left out, through no fault of their own, to less
than what those of us who are included have – actually, to far less than is
needed for the healthy development of the least advantaged, most vulnerable
children.
In a multi-level
organization of cooperative mutual support, marriages are crucial. And so is
the nurture of children, which for the most part is left primarily or
exclusively to nuclear and extended families (prior to public kindergarten in
the U.S.). Children and the nurture of children are not extrinsic to marriage
understood in this way, as part of the bigger picture. Children and the nurture
of children are an essential part of social flourishing – “for the safeguarding
and benefit of society” – because it is through healthy families that many individuals
flourish and children are nurtured to become healthy adults who can and will
contribute to large-scale cooperation for mutual support.
* * *
Finally, we
don’t need a Kantian idea of treating others as ends in themselves, which is
after all rather impersonal even if respectful. On Aristotle’s account of true
friendship, the true friend is “like another oneself” (see esp. Nicomachean Ethics, Book IX, Ch. 4, Sec.
5 and Book VIII, Ch. 12, Sec. 3). True friends care for each other for their own
sake; they enjoy spending time together; they value similar things; and they
make similar choices. Spouses can be true friends in this sense, according to
Aristotle (see esp. Nicomachean Ethics,
Book VIII, Ch. 12, Sec. 7). The Christian hope is that spouses are true friends
in this sense, and with them and the networks of friendship beyond marriage, bonds
of affection can be fostered from which ideally no one is excluded, so that
everyone is supported and enabled to thrive.
The alternative
apparently endorsed by the Task Force is to make married couples a fundamental and
independent unit and to make the nurture of children extrinsic, a merely
coincidental byproduct. But – as I will discuss in Part III – when nuclear
families are independent units, rather than parts of a larger whole (not, as
noted earlier, 1 within 2 within 3 and so on), it is far less likely that a
society can achieve the kinds of large-scale network of mutual support from
which no one is excluded and in which the dignity of every human being is respected.
It is not a
question of whether procreation is mandatory or the capacity for procreation is
essential to marriageability; it is rather a question of whether in marriage
and in other aspects of our lives we are as Christians obliged to contribute to
the larger common good beyond our marriages and extended families.
It is also not
that marriage and the nurture of children are to be mandatory, in service of
larger community. There are non-marital and non-procreative and/or
non-child-rearing ways to serve the larger community. But serving the larger
community is not optional for Christians. We are not to pursue only the aims of
our own couple, or even our own clan. We are to serve the larger community and
all humans, if not through the nurture of children, then in other ways.
Marriage and the
nurture of children are not mandatory and they do not have to go together. But
they are an essential part of a large-scale, multi-level network of circles of
affection and mutual support. We should not fail to remind ourselves of that,
even in the interest of simplifying our ideals or of leveling our estimate of
the contributions of different people and couples, so that not participating in
the nurture of children is thought to be no real loss.
* * *
Two Final
Comments:
In Essay 2, the
Task Force reflects on the concept of “complementarity” in marriage (pp. 37-38).
There is no need to reject this concept, since the relationship it identifies
simply does not require “binary-sex-difference.” Two people complement each
other when their different strengths support each other, when their different needs
are met by each other, so that, together, cooperating, they can adapt and
thrive better than they could apart. As such, complementarity is to be sought
in marriage, whether by mixed-sex or same-sex couples. It need not be thought
of as altogether sexual.
But also in
Essay 2, the Task Force offers the following peculiar claim:
Ultimately,
for those who do raise children within the context of marriage – regardless of
whether the parents and children are biologically related – parental procreativity
is fundamentally adoptive. (p. 42)
This seems to be
the or a conclusion of a curious argument on pp. 40-42. In that argument, the
“be fruitful and multiply” command in Genesis 1:28 is morphed into the injunction
to grow in Christ. This is growth we Christians are all to seek. Furthermore, being
in Christ is interpreted through St. Paul’s metaphor of the grafting of wild
olive branches onto the cultivated olive tree, which St. Paul likens to
adoption of children. So, we can be fruitful by growing in Christ only because
we were adopted into Christ’s body. Then it is acknowledged that being fruitful
can indeed sometimes take the form of procreation and the nurture of children.
But it is observed that not all marriages involve procreation and the nurture
of children. Then the conclusion quoted above is stated.
If I have
understood this peculiar chain of reasoning, it seems quite a stretch. It
appears to me to be a piece of contorted rationalization designed to level all
marriages, so that none are seen to be more central to the larger social
project of cooperative pursuit of mutual flourishing through, for instance, the
nurture of children.
But I
acknowledge that I may have failed to follow this bit of reasoning offered by
the Task Force in Essay 2.
* * *
Should we
eliminate the statement of purposes from the prologue of our marriage rite and
from the declaration of intent couples sign? Perhaps, if there were
“significant tension” between the vows and the statement of purposes which the
couple signs. Is there? No, not unless we ignore the basis of much catholic
moral theology for centuries in preference for Enlightenment and
post-Enlightenment moral theory.
* * *
In “Suffer the
little children,” Part III, I will offer reflections on how the mistaken
reasoning in Essay 1 seems to block recognition of evidence offered in Essays 4
& 7. That evidence, I will suggest, reveals the kind of social
disintegration we find in some liberal cultures, which should provide a
cautionary tale about moving away from stating and teaching about the purposes
of marriage as including the nurture of children “for the safeguarding and
benefit of society.” I will also offer reflections on the common ground that we
might find between traditionalists and progressives.